Sarah Song knows a thing or two about immigration. Born in
South Korea, she immigrated to the United States with her parents when she was
six years old. After having to repeat the first grade because she didn’t speak English,
she went on to earn an M.Phil in politics from Oxford and a Ph.D in political
science from Yale. She is now a professor of law and political science at the
University of California, Berkeley, where her work centers on issues of immigration,
citizenship, and multiculturalism.
Song’s second book, Immigration
and Democracy, is the product of years of careful thinking about
immigration and its role in democratic societies. The arguments presented here
are grounded in a deep understanding of political theory, providing a necessary
corrective to the crude sloganeering that too often shapes our public discourse
on immigration policy. As Song states in her preface, she has written the book
in the hope “that we can move beyond an ‘us versus them’ mentality and engage
in reasoned debate about immigration.”
The book is divided into three parts. In Part I, Song
examines various justifications for the state’s power over immigration. These
include the “plenary power” doctrine articulated by the U.S. Supreme
Court—which Song characterizes as “more assertion than argument”—as well as the
writings of a number of philosophers and political theorists. Building upon the
theory of collective self-determination, Song argues that the “right to control
immigration is part of the bundle of territorial rights necessary for peoples
to be self-determining.” This right, however, is not absolute. It is qualified
by other, competing rights, such as the rights of refugees fleeing violence or
persecution.
In Part II, Song examines the arguments in favor of open
borders. These are of two basic kinds: global distributive justice arguments
and rights-based arguments. Global distributive justice arguments are generally
concerned with alleviating global poverty. If all borders were open, the
thinking goes, then people born in poor countries would be free to seek
economic opportunities elsewhere. But as Song points out, “it is typically not
the world’s poorest who migrate, and the departure of a country’s more-skilled
members tends to deepen, not mitigate, global inequality.” While recognizing
that wealthier nations have a certain moral obligation to help alleviate global
poverty, Song argues that development assistance is a more effective solution
than open borders.
She then goes on to consider rights-based arguments for open
borders, which invoke widely recognized rights such as freedom of movement,
freedom of association, and freedom of contract. Song finds that all of these
arguments fall short of justifying open borders. She notes that individual
rights must be weighed against competing rights, including the right of a
people to self-determination. Furthermore, rights-based arguments “are
indifferent to the reasons people have for wanting to migrate…. [A] compelling
normative theory of migration should be able to distinguish and prioritize
among different reasons for migration.”
In Part III, Song considers the various circumstances under
which people migrate, and attempts to lay out a framework for democratic
societies to consider when formulating immigration policy. She does this by
drawing a distinction between what she calls “obligatory admissions” and “discretionary
admissions.” Obligatory admissions include refugees and certain types of
family-based immigration claims. Discretionary admissions include those who
migrate for purely voluntary reasons. “Many migrants fall somewhere in between,
and there is reasonable disagreement about where to draw the line,” Song
writes, “but I believe it is important to maintain some distinction between
those who have fundamental interests that can only be met through migration and
those who do not. Doing away with the distinction altogether would leave us
without any way to prioritize truly necessitous migrants.” She then goes on to
discuss the criteria states may use when considering discretionary admissions,
whether for temporary-worker programs or for permanent residence, and concludes
with a discussion of the rights of non-citizens in the territory.
Immigration and
Democracy is an illuminating and well-argued book that deserves the
attention of anyone interested in a serious and nuanced approach to immigration
policy. It is now available on the New Books shelf at the O’Quinn Law Library.
Comments
Post a Comment